The Myth of the Evil Grey Squirrel

 

 

 

INTRODUCTION

This piece of writing started its life as a talk at an animal festival. The brief to me from the organizers was myth-busting, and the Myth of the Evil Grey Squirrel can be formulated as follows: they are an invasive alien species, they replace the native red squirrel, destroy trees and reduce the bird population.

These accusations do not usually survive an encounter with general knowledge on the subject. The argument is very often in the detail, but what I would like to do here is give a general overview of the red squirrels, trees and birds issues,then dwell on the language that the myth is formulated in, and end with putting our attitude to the grey squirrel in the wider context of ethics, thus attempting to answer the question of why the myth takes hold in society.

 

THE GREYS AND THE RED                                                                                                        wp_20160403_029

The first and the most serious accusation against grey squirrels is that they replace the native red squirrel. As with all myths, there is a small factual base, and a cloud of fiction around it. It is true that the grey squirrel is not native to this country (in the sense in which it is appropriate to talk of “native” on territory that was scraped clean by ice 10 000 years ago). They were introduced from America in the 19th century, at a time when it was fashionable to move animals between continents. It is also true that now there are between 2 and 3 million greys and between 150 and 200 thousand reds, quite a difference. But this is where the facts end.

Red squirrel became virtually extinct in Great Britain before greys were introduced (because of habitat loss), so it follows logically that, even if every grey squirrel was killed (and very few people would support cruelty on such a scale), the reds would not thrive now any more than they did then, since the habitat has only got worse. (Harris, et al., ‘Is culling of grey squirrels a viable tactic to conserve red squirrel populations?’, Bristol University, 2008. Middleton, The Ecology of the American Grey Squirrel in the British Isles, 1930.)

Plus, the red squirrels living in this country today are themselves products of recent Scandinavian introductions and hybrids with them, not the original British squirrel. (Hale, et al., ‘Patterns of genetic diversity in the red squirrel (Sciurus vulgaris L.): Footprints of biogeographic history and artificial introductions.’, University of Newcastle, 2003.)

There are projects in this country that claim to prove that their killing grey squirrels helps the reds to come back, but if you look closer at what is happening there, you will find that the red squirrels are artificially maintained – with captive breeding programmes, feeding stations, nest boxes, like a large zoo. It is hardly moral to kill off one species that fits the habitat well and artificially maintain another, that you prefer for sentimental reasons, even though it cannot survive in this habitat unaided.

However, in areas where the habitat is still right for red squirrels, they do coexist with the greys, e.g. Bryce et al., ‘Can niche use in red and grey squirrels offer clues for their apparent coexistence?’, Journal of Applied Ecology, 2002.

Another factor that is mentioned in this connection the the pox virus. It kill red squirrels (thought they are slowly developing immunity to it), whereas the more robust greys carry the virus without becoming ill themselves. This fact leads to the accusation that greys are killing reds with the pox virus. This accusation, however, does not take into account the actual process of disease transmission. In practice the vast majority of the reds do not get the pox from the greys, but from fellow reds. In most areas where the disease first broke out at the beginning of the 20th century there were no grey squirrels at all. In fact, grey squirrels are only indirectly to blame for the pox, whereas the artificial maintenance of red squirrel colonies in England can be blamed directly: feeding stations cause a high concentration of animals in one place, which provides ideal conditions for the virus to spread. 

These considerations lead to the following conclusion: ‘It is widely argued that controlling grey squirrel numbers is the best way of conserving red squirrels. However, there is little evidence to support this belief.’ (Harris, et al., Bristol University, 2008.)

 

THE TREES                                                                                                                              13653024_1750311255226153_9007707469396163402_o

The second accusation is that squirrels destroy trees. It seems utterly bizarre, since the very opposite is the case: squirrels are some of nature’s greatest conservationists, they regenerate forests. They cashe seeds and nuts, and actually eat the bad ones first, thus planting new trees. Numerous studies show that squirrels are essential for forest regeneration.

The small factual basis for the myth is that squirrels, both reds and greys, feed on trees. They eat leaves, buds, twigs; they also strip some bark in order to get to the sap, the jelly, underneath. This, however, does not kill the vast majority of trees. It prunes some branches, it changes the look of the tree, but does not kill the tree. It is, of course, theoretically possible that in old fragile trees the bark stripping will make the tree vulnerable to disease and kill it. The tree would then fall down and become an important wildlife habitat in its own right, while squirrels plant new trees in its stead. It is the circle of life!

Where squirrel chewing can cause a problem is in commercial forestry, hence the cloud of myth around the fact. But even here a sense of proportion is essential. Squirrel chewing causes cosmetic damage to trees destined for human consumption. And in the section of the industry that produces pulp, paper, construction timber, etc., it clearly does not matter. Even in the middle-range market – pine furniture, oak furniture, wooden floors – imperfections are seen as part of the natural charm of the wood. Where it does matter is in the luxury market, the kind of trees that are going to be harvested in 80 years time. But even then it is by no means every tree that is affected, we are talking about a fraction of a fraction of the industry. And I, for my part, hope that in 80 years’ time we will have a very different relationship with both squirrels and trees.

 

THE BIRDS                                                                                         robin-2

The last accusation is that squirrel reduce the bird population. It is actually a quick one to deal with, because an extensive, government-funded study has been conducted and concluded that it is not the case. ‘Analyses of large-scale and extensive national monitoring data provides little underlying evidence for large-scale impacts of widespread avian predators and grey squirrels on avian prey population’ (Newson et al., 2009).

It is true that squirrels are opportunistic feeders, and, if they come across an unattended nest, they might take an egg. But they are not predators, they will not deliberately seek out eggs or hunt chicks, and what they do is statistically negligible. Furthermore, the bark-stripping actually assists birds, because it encourages fungus-growth and it encourages insects, food for birds.

 

THE LANGUAGE THE MYTH IS FORMULATED IN                                       14424883_1769667319957213_2891307741807778377_o

A vocabulary analysis is essential to myth busting, since some concepts can appear neutral, but are in fact ideologically loaded, and we can unwittingly concede a lot of ground in a debate simply by committing ourselves to certain terminology. In the Myth of the Evil Grey Squirrel such loaded words are alien, invasive, and, perhaps surprisingly, species.

As a culture, we are so enthralled by the “native good, alien bad” mantra, that we do not even stop to consider how completely irrational it is. It is purely a question of fashion. In the 19th century the fashion was the opposite, it was fashionable to collect plants and animals from all over the British Empire and to try to establish them on different continents. It was called acclimatization. Kew Gardens was a holding ground from plants from all over the empire. There was an acclimatization society for animals as well. Now the pendulum has swung in the opposite direction, and alien species are, as far as conventional conservation is concerned, public enemy number one. But no one seems to want to ask exactly why natives are good and aliens are bad.

Fortunately, there are some notable exceptions to this tendency. The case of alien species has been brilliantly taken up by Fred Pearce in his book “The New Wild”, subtitle “Why invasive species will be nature’s salvation”, which offers an important alternative paradigm in conservation, an alternative to what the author calls “invasion biology” that demonizes alien species. Fred Pearce argues that the “native good, alien bad” approach is irrational. The vast majority of alien species do no harm whatsoever. Even in the rare cases where they do become a problem, such as the Nile perch in Lake Victoria, or the killer algae of the Mediterranean, it is man-made pollution that made the waters susceptible to the invasion, a healthy ecosystem would have fought off the newcomers in the first place. Furthermore, some alien species are in fact beneficial, they seem to be nature’s way of coping with the ecological problems we have created, they reboot the ecosystem, as it were, and can pave a way for natives to return. We may agree or disagree with this analysis, but in either case it is worth noting that the words alien and native are loaded, not neutral, terms.

“Invasive” is another such term. If I say that grey squirrels are “successful”, “adaptable”, “highly intelligent”, the science behind the phrases would be exactly the same. And yet the term “invasive”, with its emotional undertone of “help, we are being invaded” persists in the public discourse. Perhaps a more neutral expression “wide-spread” should be used in order to keep the language impartial?

The word “species” is also not as innocent as it appears either. The problem is that it has different applications in science and in ethics. In science it is a very precise term, everyone knows where a species begins and ends. It is necessary for it to be like that, so that scientists can study and communicate with each other. In ethics, however, species is a flexible term, it simply determines the correct level of generalization in a particular discussion. It was defined as such by the philosopher Porphyry in Late Antiquity, in his hugely influential “Isagogue”, introduction to Aristotle’s “Categories”. For him, species is a sliding term. We can say, for example, that animals are a genus and cats, dogs and horses are species within it. Or we can say that cats are a genus, and lions, tigers and domestic cats are species. Or we can say, if the discussion warrants it, that domestic cats are a genus, and the species within it are different breeds of domestic cats.

This seems unusual and awkward, but it is actually very helpful in ethical discussions, because it allows us to keep hold of both equality and individuality. For instance, in a discussion about cancer screening, men, women and children are all different species with different needs, they are not equal. However, if we talk about access to medical care, they are all one species, they are equal. But if we talk about treating a person, then no level of generalization is appropriate at all, they should receive care as an individual.

If, however, we keep the concept of species rigid in ethics, we run into all sorts of problems. Speciesism, for a start. Also we can forget that species is not an absolute given, but an intellectual tool (a very useful one, of course), for humanity to study the world they live in. It can be used in study, but not as justification for killing some animals in order to help others. Such justification would not be logical, because it takes the concept of species outside its legitimate sphere of application in philosophy.

The associated concept of biodiversity is equally problematic. When I first read the animal ethicist’s Andrew Lindzey’s words that the concept of biodiversity is philosophically vacuous, I was a bit shocked. We are so accustomed to thinking of biodiversity as a supreme, absolute, obvious good. However, who ultimately decides how diverse is diverse enough? It is a human agenda. If human being promote biodiversity by benign means, it is fine. However, if they do it by killing some animals in order to help others, it is a lot more ethically questionable.

 

THE WIDER CONTEXT                                                                            rose-20160528_130

It is interesting to look at why the Myth of the Evil Grey Squirrel takes hold in society, in spite of being intellectually untenable. It is, of course, impossible to come up with a definitive answer, but a few things do come to mind. Grants are given to land-owners to “control” (kill) grey squirrels.  This may be another way of passing public money to the countryside, perhaps in response to some kind of powerful lobbying. The myth would be needed as propaganda to justify this particular instance of institutional corruption.

A follow-on question is why the public puts up with it. After all, if we stopped someone in the street and told them that there is no money for hospitals, or schools, or benefits for the disabled, but there is plenty of money for people to kill squirrels, that person would not be happy, as a tax-payer, even if they did not care about animals. But the problem is, grants to kill squirrels are a small part in the budget as a whole. In comparison, for instance, with subsidies to farmers, an arrangement where huge amounts of public money go to relatively wealthy people to maintain their unprofitable lifestyle businesses.

Another reason for people putting up with the expense and the cruelty is that they actually subscribe to the evil squirrel myth – not because they are intellectually persuaded by it, but because it agrees with their prejudices against the grey squirrel in daily life (squirrels raid the bird-feeders, dig up bulbs in the garden, etc.). As conflicts with wildlife go, this seems incredible trivial, and the solutions are easy. In the case of bird-feeders one can use a separate feeder for squirrels, or buy a good squirrel-proof one for the birds. For bulbs, cayenne pepper, or commercial deterrents, can be used to deter furry guerrilla-gardeners.

But the will to find a solution very often is not there. This happens because of a certain mind-set in relation to non-human animals in general. This mind-set dictates that human interests, however trivial, will always trump non-human ones, even if the human interests in question are replaceable ones, and the non-human vital. In other words, if an animal interferes with as much as a hobby, it is OK to kill the animal. In philosophical language, this mind-set does not acknowledge any intrinsic moral status of non-human animals.

However much we despair when we come face-to-face with this attitude, it is encouraging to remember that it is shifting in favour of non-human animals. It is precisely in the social aspect of ethics (which determines whom we consider ourselves to have moral obligations to) that historical progress can be discerned, if it can be discerned at all. Rescue efforts, advocacy, public campaigns all serve to bring about this social change, and there is no doubt that, both legally and practically, animal welfare has moved on a lot in the last 20 or 30 years. Although, obviously, there is still a staggeringly long way to go, witness the case of the grey squirrel.


 

    OFFER HELP AS A FEEDING VOLUNTEER. BECOME A VOLUNTEER